Klein, Carsten Conventionalism and realism in Hans Reichenbach’s philosophy of geometry. (English) Zbl 1042.00004 Int. Stud. Philos. Sci. 15, No. 3, 243-251 (2001). The author argues against the standard interpretation of Hans Reichenbach’s geometrical conventionalism as being an example of positivistic philosophy of science connected to a verificationist theory of meaning. In analyzing H. Reichenbach’s early philosophy of space and time as presented in his “Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre” [Leipzig and Berlin, de Gruyter (1928; JFM 54.0937.17); English ed. “Philosophy of Space and Time” (New York, Dover) (1958; Zbl 0084.00307)], the author arrives at the conclusion that Reichenbach’s conventionalism rather turns out to be “a specific form of scientific realism, which exactly avoids to identify factual content and empirical content” (p.243). The argument starts from the assertion that “Reichenbach’s so-called geometric conventionalism consists in the claim that there are equivalent geometric descriptions of physical space” (p.244), but Reichenbach, nevertheless, preserves the concept of an objective reality as one that is independent of our descriptions. According to the author, this is the central idea of Reichenbach early philosophy of geometry. This evaluation is supported by Reichenbach’s criticism of Henri Poincaré’s conventionalism which he interpreted as radical geometrical relativism. The theory of equivalent descriptions tries to avoid this relativistic consequence. It was put forward for “preserving a certain kind of scientific realism while at the same time maintaining a moderate conventionalism” (p.249). Reviewer: Volker Peckhaus (Paderborn) MSC: 00A30 Philosophy of mathematics 01A60 History of mathematics in the 20th century Keywords:physical geometry; geometrical conventionalism; realism; theory of equivalent descriptions Citations:JFM 54.0937.17; Zbl 0084.00307 PDFBibTeX XMLCite \textit{C. Klein}, Int. Stud. Philos. Sci. 15, No. 3, 243--251 (2001; Zbl 1042.00004) Full Text: DOI References: [1] CARNAP, R. 1958. ”Introductory remarks to the English edition”. Edited by: REICHENBACH. vii (1958) [2] FRIEDMAN M., Foundations of Space-Time Theories (1983) [3] GLYMOUR C., Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science VIII pp 275– (1971) [4] GRÜNBAUM A., Geometry and Chronometry in Philosophical Perspective (1968) · Zbl 0194.30402 [5] GRÜNBAUM A., Philosophical Problems of Space and Time,, 2. ed. (1973) · Zbl 0299.50001 [6] KAMLAH A., Gesammelte Werke, Bd. 2: Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre pp 389– (1977) [7] MÜHLHÖLZER F., Erkenntnis 35 pp 77– (1991) [8] MÜHLHÖLZER F., Logic, Language and the Structure of Scientific Theories, Proceedings of the Carnap-Reichenbach Centennial Konstanz 1991 pp 119– (1994) [9] POINCARE H., Science and Hypotheses (1952) [10] DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511625251.011 · doi:10.1017/CBO9780511625251.011 [11] DOI: 10.1007/BF00178004 · doi:10.1007/BF00178004 [12] DOI: 10.1515/9783111485676 · doi:10.1515/9783111485676 [13] REICHENBACH H., The Philosophy of Space and Time (1958) · Zbl 0082.01301 [14] DOI: 10.1007/BF01130757 · doi:10.1007/BF01130757 [15] STEGMÜLLER W., Probleme und Resultate der Wissemchaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie, Bd. 2: Theorie und Erfahrung (1970) · Zbl 0211.00701 [16] ZITTLAU D., Die Philosophie von Hans Reichenbach (1981) This reference list is based on information provided by the publisher or from digital mathematics libraries. Its items are heuristically matched to zbMATH identifiers and may contain data conversion errors. In some cases that data have been complemented/enhanced by data from zbMATH Open. This attempts to reflect the references listed in the original paper as accurately as possible without claiming completeness or a perfect matching.