Meier, Martin Finitely additive beliefs and universal type spaces. (English) Zbl 1161.91009 Ann. Probab. 34, No. 1, 386-422 (2006). Summary: The probabilistic type spaces in the sense of J. C. Harsanyi [Manage. Sci., Theory 14, 159–182 (1967; Zbl 0207.51102), 320–334 (1968; Zbl 0177.48402), 486–502 (1968; Zbl 0177.48501)] are the prevalent models used to describe interactive uncertainty. In this paper we examine the existence of a universal type space when beliefs are described by finitely additive probability measures. We find that in the category of all type spaces that satisfy certain measurability conditions (\(\kappa\)-measurability, for some fixed regular cardinal \(\kappa\)), there is a universal type space (i.e., a terminal object) to which every type space can be mapped in a unique beliefs-preserving way. However, by a probabilistic adaption of the elegant sober-drunk example of A. Heifetz and D. Samet [Games Econ. Behav. 22, No. 2, 260–273 (1998; Zbl 0895.90201)] we show that if all subsets of the spaces are required to be measurable, then there is no universal type space. Cited in 10 Documents MSC: 91A40 Other game-theoretic models 91A35 Decision theory for games 28A10 Real- or complex-valued set functions 60A05 Axioms; other general questions in probability Citations:Zbl 0207.51102; Zbl 0177.48402; Zbl 0177.48501; Zbl 0895.90201 PDF BibTeX XML Cite \textit{M. Meier}, Ann. Probab. 34, No. 1, 386--422 (2006; Zbl 1161.91009) Full Text: DOI arXiv References: [1] Aumann, R. J. and Brandenburger, A. (1995). Epistemic conditions for Nash equilibrium. Econometrica 63 1161–1180. · Zbl 0841.90125 [2] Battigalli, P. and Siniscalchi, M. (1999). Interactive beliefs and forward induction. Working Paper ECO 99/15, European Univ. Institute. · Zbl 0972.91020 [3] Brandenburger, A. and Dekel, E. (1993). Hierarchies of beliefs and common knowledge. J. Econom. Theory 59 189–198. · Zbl 0773.90109 [4] Devlin, K. (1993). The Joy of Sets , 2nd ed. Springer, New York. · Zbl 0792.04001 [5] Harsanyi, J. C. (1967/68). Games with incomplete information played by Bayesian players, I–III. Management Sci. 14 159–182, 320–334, 486–502. · Zbl 0207.51102 [6] Heifetz, A. (1993). The Bayesian formulation of incomplete information—the noncompact case. Internat. J. Game Theory 21 329–338. · Zbl 0794.90009 [7] Heifetz, A. (2002). Limitations of the syntactic approach. In Handbook of Game Theory 3 (R. J. Aumann and S. Hart, eds.) 1682–1684. North-Holland, Amsterdam. [8] Heifetz, A. and Mongin, P. (2001). Probability logic for type spaces. Games Econom. Behav. 35 31–53. · Zbl 0978.03017 [9] Heifetz, A. and Samet, D. (1998). Knowledge spaces with arbitrarily high rank. Games Econom. Behav. 22 260–273. · Zbl 0895.90201 [10] Heifetz, A. and Samet, D. (1998). Topology-free typology of beliefs. J. Econom. Theory 82 324–341. · Zbl 0921.90156 [11] Horn, A. and Tarski, A. (1948). Measures in Boolean algebras. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 64 467–497. · Zbl 0035.03001 [12] Łoś, J. and Marczewski, E. (1949). Extensions of measure. Fund. Math. 36 267–276. · Zbl 0039.05202 [13] Mertens, J. F., Sorin, S. and Zamir, S. (1994). Repeated games. Part A. Background material. CORE Discussion Paper 9420, Univ. Catholique de Louvain. · Zbl 0448.90080 [14] Mertens, J. F. and Zamir, S. (1985). Formulation of Bayesian analysis for games with incomplete information. Internat. J. Game Theory 14 1–29. · Zbl 0567.90103 [15] Savage, L. J. (1954, 1972). The Foundations of Statistics . New York, Wiley. [Second edition (1972) Dover, New York.] · Zbl 0276.62006 [16] Stalnaker, R. (1998). Belief revision in games: Forward and backward induction. Math. Social. Sci. 36 31–56. · Zbl 0963.91016 This reference list is based on information provided by the publisher or from digital mathematics libraries. Its items are heuristically matched to zbMATH identifiers and may contain data conversion errors. It attempts to reflect the references listed in the original paper as accurately as possible without claiming the completeness or perfect precision of the matching.